MATHEMATICAL EXPLANATION: WHY IT
MATTERS
(From The Book Philosophy of Mathematical
Pratice ByPaolo Mancosu)
to complete the task of Science
Philosophy Course
Lecturer : Dr. LailaFitriana,
M.Pd.

Heri Satriawan
POSTGRADUATE OF MATHEMATICS EDUCATION
FACULTY OF TEACHER TRAINING AND EDUCATION
UNIVERSITAS SEBELAS MARET
SURAKARTA
2018
CHAPTER
1
INTRODUCTION
A.
Background
The last two decades
have witnessed a significant increase of attention to mathematical explanation,
both in science and mathematics. This has led to novel joint work between
philosophers of science and philosophers of mathematics.The philosophical
analysis of mathematical explanations concerns itself with two different,
although connected, areas of investigation.
The first area
addresses the question of whether mathematics can play an explicit role in the
natural and social sciences (mathematical explanation of scientific facts). A
mathematical explanation of scientific facts based on a clear phenomenon with
detailed information and minimizing the significance of error by explanation.
The second offering with the problem of whether mathematical explanation occurs
in mathematics itself (mathematical explanation of mathematical facts).
Mathematical explanation of mathematical facts based on formal evidence and
informal evidence. Formal evidence is basically the logical form of the set of
premises and axioms. Whereas, informal proof is a form of proof that aims to
conclude a new statement based on a previously known statement. The difference
in informal proofs is more likely to be in the form of paragraphs than in
logical forms. Thus, these entries survey contributions to both fields, it
shows their relevance to the history of philosophy, mathematics, and science,
it articulates their connections, and points to the expected philosophy by
deepening our understanding of the topic. Mathematical applications occur in a
natural phenomenon studied science is then described using mathematics or when
the problem to be solved by science is answered by using mathematical
techniques.
Based on consideration,
the evidence of mathematical explanation can be generalized rationally, those
that are not so the 'generalization' stipulations which fail to illuminate
those areas of mathematics which have already been developed are not rationally
acceptable. The process of generalization rationality in mathematics, also need
a mathematical explanation. Only significant generalizations can explain
rational changes in mathematics. Thus, it should be clear how the need for a
mathematical explanatory theory appears in generalization. The explanatory
theory requires that the explanatory evidence be generalizable. To uncover
these problems, then all will be explained in this paper.
B.
Problem
Formulation
Based on the background issues, the
problems discussed can be formulated as follows:
1. Why
is the matter of mathematical explanation of scientific facts to mathematical
explanations of mathematical facts?
2. What
is the connection of explanation and generalization in mathematics?
C.
The
Aim of Research
Based
on the problem formulation, the aims of the research are:
1. To
know the matterof mathematical explanation of scientific facts to mathematical
explanations of mathematical facts.
2. To
know the connection of explanation and generalization in mathematics.
CHAPTER
2
FINDINGS
AND DISCUSSION
5.1
Mathematical Explanations of Scientific Facts
The mathematical explanations of natural
phenomena are widely recognized in the literature. However, until now very
little attention has been devoted to them. The mathematical explanations of
natural phenomena articulate how the explanation of how mathematics relates to
reality, for example the explanation of the application of mathematics to
reality. Illustrative example: a bunch of sticks thrown into the air with many
turns and falls. When the stick falls freely, the stick is more near the
horizontal than near the vertical. Broadly speaking, the facts of geometry can
explain the cause.
The mathematical explanation of
empirical phenomena can not be used to infer the existence of a mathematical
entity, since existence is presupposed in the factual description to be
explained. In other words, the existence of a mathematical entity can not be
observed by the human senses. Example: "there are two cows in the
field" the existence of number two can not be explained in a physical
statement, since clear reference to number two can be explained by using the
standard of the numeric number. The mathematical explanations of the empirical
facts have not been sufficiently studied, as much detailed case study is needed
to understand the various uses of explanations that mathematics can play in an
empirical context.
Philosophical advantage may come from at
least three different directions. First, towards a better understanding of the
application of mathematics to the world, that is how mathematics can help in
scientific explanations. Second, the study of mathematical explanations of
scientific facts will serve as a causal explanation (causation). Thirdly, the
arguments and forcing nominalist discussions take a stand on how to explain the
clarity of mathematics in empirical science
5.2
From
Mathematical Explanations of
Scientific Facts to
Mathematical Explanations of
Mathematical Facts
In an interesting note to her
paper Leng says:
Given the form of Baker
and Colyvan’s argument, one might wonder whyit is mathematical explanations of physical
phenomena that get priority. For ifthere are, as we have suggested, some
genuine mathematical explanations [ofmathematical facts] then these
explanations must also have true explanans. Thereason that this argument can’t
be used is that, in the context of an argument forrealism about mathematics, it
is question begging. For we also assume here thatgenuine explanations must have
a true explanandum, and when the explanandumis mathematical, its truth will
also be in question. (2005, p. 174)
This comment reflects the general use to
which indispensability arguments. just
as standard indispensability arguments address those who are realists
abouttheoretical entities in science, so here the intended audience for the
argumentwould consist of those who are realists about a certain realm of
mathematicalentities (say, the natural numbers) and in addition are not already
committedto a foundational position (such as predicativism) which forbids
entertainingthe entities being postulated by the explanationhave
been put.
The indispensability argument is not
endorsed for mathematics. The original form of the indispensability argument
relied on a form of confirmational holism. This left the argument open to the
objection, raised forcefully by Maddy, that scientific practice proceeds
otherwise or to the objection that other accounts of confirmation block the
conclusion (Sober, 1993). In response, advocates like Colyvan and Baker have
argued that explanatory considerations lead to platonism even if we drop
conformational holism. But, as pointed out, nobody really has an account of
mathematical explanations of scientific phenomena.
Quine originally used the
indispensability argument to argue that we should believe in sets because they
do the best job in tracking all our commitments to abstract objects. For Quine
the appeal to empirical science was essential. Maddy’s realism drops the
connection to empirical science and tries to obtain the same conclusion just by
focusing on pure mathematics. In Chapter 4 of Maddy (1990) we find a lengthy
discussion of theoretical virtues, including explanatory ones, that play a role
in ‘extrinsic’ justifications for axiom choice in set theory. And althoughMaddy
herself gave up the attempt in favor of ‘naturalism’ (see Maddy (1997)), mathematical
explanation can still play an important role in this debate.
For those who believe that her realism
can be revived perhaps the detour through indispensability arguments that
appeal to mathematical explanations might provide a more persuasive type of argument than the other varieties of ‘extrinsic’
justifications mentioned in 1990. Moreover, those who are persuaded by the
‘naturalist’ approach of her latest book will as a matter of fact have to
welcome investigations into mathematical explanation as they are part and
parcel of the kind of work the methodologist in this area ought to carry out.
So both these options call for an account of mathematical explanations of
mathematical facts.
5.3
Mathematical
explanations of mathematical facts
The history of the philosophy of
mathematics shows that a major conceptual role has been played by the
opposition between proofs that convince but do not explain and proofs that in
addition to providing the required conviction that the result is true also show
why it is true. This philosophical opposition between types of proof also
influenced mathematical practice and led many of its supporters often to
criticize existing mathematical practice for its epistemological inadequacy.
Steiner’s model of explanation, to be discussed below, although not relying on
the Aristotelian opposition, aims at characterizing the distinction between
explanatory and non-explanatory proofs.
Hence what distinguishes an explanatory
proof from a non-explanatory one is that only the former involves such a
characterizing property. In Steiner’s words: ‘an explanatory proof makes
reference to a characterizing property of an entity or structure mentioned in
the theorem, such that from the proof it is evident that the result depends on
the property’. Furthermore, an explanatory proof is generalizable in the
following sense. Varying the relevant feature (and hence a certain
characterizing property) in such a proof gives rise to an array of
corresponding theorems, which are proved—and explained—by an array of
‘deformations’ of the original proof. Thus Steiner arrives at two criteria for
explanatory proofs, i.e. dependence on a characterizing property and
generalizability through varying of that property (Steiner,1978a, pp. 144,
147).
According to Steiner, an explanatory
proof always makes reference to a characterizing property of an entity or
structure mentioned in the theorem. Furthermore, it must be evident that the
result depends on the property (if we substitute the entity for another entity
in the family which does not have the property, the proof fails to go through)
and that by suitably `deforming' the proof while holding the `proof-idea'
constant, we can get a proof of a related theorem. Though many of Steiner's
concepts (family, deformation, proof-idea) are vague, we can construct examples
which beyond any doubt would classify as explanatory proofs by his criterion.Steiner’s
model was criticized by Resnik and Kushner (1987) who questioned the absolute
distinction between explanatory and non-explanatory proofs and argued that such
a distinction can only be context-dependent.
5.4
Kitcher
about explanations and generalizations
According to Curnot generalizations are
generated because they reveal a common basic principle in thinking derived from
certain truths, connections and common origins that had not previously been
seen, found in all sciences, and especially in mathematics. Such generalization
is the most important generalization, and their invention is a work of genius.
Sterile generalization consists of the expansion of nonessential cases
populated by inventive people for important cases, leaving the rest on a
visible analogy. In such cases, a further step towards abstraction and
generalization does not mean improvement in the order of mathematical explanations.
What distinguishes both is that the first is the second temporary explanation
not. According to Cournot generalizations were able to express the sequence of
explanations in accordance with the mathematical truths that are structured.
Mandelbrojt says that generalizations
are informative and clear. Such generalizations can be obtained with the proper
level of abstraction and should show the learned object in the "natural
setting". Eventually both Cournot and Mandelbrojt regarded it as having a
mathematical explanation.
Kitcher discusses the problem of
generalization in his book The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge from 1984. In
his book according to Kitcher One of the most easily visible patterns of
mathematical change, so far not explicitly discussed is the extension of the
Mathematical Language by generalizations. For example Kitcher mentions
Reimann's redefinition of definite integrals, Hamilton's search for
hypercomplex numbers, and generalization of citing of limited arithmetic.
Kitcher's goal is to try to understand the generalization process that takes
place and to see how generalization's search becomes rational. However, not all
generalizations are significant. Significant generalization is explanation.
They explain to us exactly how, by modifying certain rules which are
constitutive of the use of some Language expressions.
Kitcher tries to distinguish between
rational and non-acceptable generalizations. The generalization provisions that
fail to explain the areas of mathematics that have been developed can not be
accepted rationally. In other words, to explain the rationality of the
generalization process in mathematics, we need mathematical explanations. Thus
it must be clear how the theoretical need for mathematical explanations arises
on generalizations. Only significant generalizations can explain rational
change in mathematics and that is explanatory. From the above description then
the mathematical explanation should be generalizable, with evidence generally
applicable.
CHAPTER III
CONCLUSION
The conclution of the explanation
about mathematical explanation: why it matters are
1.
The
mathematical explanation of scientific facts is an explanation of how
mathematics relates to reality and is informed in detail of its physical form,
whether in the natural sciences or in the social sciences. Meanwhile, a
mathematical explanation of mathematical facts based on explanatory
proof and non-explanatory
proof. What
distinguishes an explanatory proof from a non-explanatory one is that only the
former involves such a characterizing property. An
explanatory proof always makes reference to a characterizing property of an
entity or structure mentioned in the theorem.
2.
Generalization is
informative and clear. Such generalizations can be obtained with the proper
level of abstraction and should show the learned object in the "natural
setting", which in general there is a mathematical explanation with
general evidences.
No comments:
Post a Comment